Did Rationalism Die In Islam With Averroes? Are Theologians Philosophers?

( Interesting article by Peter Adamson on Islamic Philosophers, role of theologians, especially ” Kalam” in philosophy and its place in Western Philosophy f.sheikh)

May be I’m just an optimist, but I think people today mostly acknowledge the importance and originality of philosophy in the Islamic world. Would any scholar now say in print, as Bertrand Russell notoriously did in his History of Western Philosophy (written in 1945), that ‘Arabic philosophy is not important as original thought. Men like Avicenna and Averroes are essentially commentators’? I certainly hope not. But even if we now see more clearly, we still have blindspots. The thinkers taken seriously as ‘philosophers’ are typically the authors Russell dismissed as mere commentators, men such as al-Kindī, al-Fārābī, Avicenna, and Averroes. Though they were far from unoriginal, they were indeed enthusiasts for Aristotle and other Greek authors. Yet these were not the only intellectuals and rationalists of their time, nor did rationalism and philosophical reflection die with Averroes at the end of the 12th century, as is still often believed. Throughout Islamic history, many of the figures of interest and relevance to the historian of philosophy were not Aristotelians, but practitioners of kalām, which is usually translated as ‘theology’.

The word kalām literally means ‘word’, and here abbreviates the Arabic expression ʿilm al-kalām: ‘science of the word’. It is often contrasted to the term falsafa, which as you can probably guess was imported into Arabic as a loan-word from the Greek philosophia. When modern-day scholars draw this contrast, when they assume that kalām was non-philosophical or even anti-philosophical, they are taking their lead from the medieval tradition itself. In particular, from two self-styled ‘philosophers (falāsifa)’, al-Fārābī and Averroes. In their eyes, the ‘theologians (mutakallimūn)’ engaged in mere dialectical argumentation; whereas philosophy offers demonstrative proofs. The theologian does not ground arguments in first principles, but just defends his own favourite interpretation of scripture against rival interpretations. Averroes was scornful of the results, complaining that it can lead to violent schism. For him, only a philosopher can offer a really reliable reading of the Quran, since the philosopher knows what is true on independent grounds – that is, on the grounds of Aristotelian science.

But should we accept this sharp opposition? These Aristotelians talk as if kalām makes insufficient use of reason. But most contemporaries would have seen it as controversial precisely because it was so rationalist. Theologians often departed from the surface meaning of the Quran on rational grounds: Revelation might seem to speak of God as if He had a body, but we can rule this out by giving arguments against His corporeality. The mutakallimūn also engaged in detailed disputes over such central philosophical issues as free will, atomism and the sources of moral responsibility, and debated such technicalities as the inherence of properties in substances, or the status of non-existing objects. If history had gone differently and there had been no hard-line Aristotelians writing in Arabic, I have no doubt that historians of philosophy would consider the output of the mutakallimūn to be the ‘philosophical’ tradition of the Islamic world.

That would have made our approach to Islamic intellectual history more like our treatment of Christian medieval thought. After all, medieval philosophy classes are mostly devoted to figures who considered themselves to be ‘theologians’, such as Anselm, Aquinas, Duns Scotus, and William of Ockham. Of course, there are plenty of people who don’t like medieval philosophy either, precisely because of its religious context. But my view is that philosophy is where you find it, and that it is narrow-minded to ignore philosophical argumentation put forward by thinkers simply because they have a religious agenda, whether that agenda grows out of Christianity (as with Aquinas), Judaism (as with Maimonides), Hinduism (as with Nyāya epistemology or Vedānta philosophy of mind), or Islam.

The refusal to appreciate the philosophical interest of kalām is especially pernicious when it comes to the period after the pivotal figure of philosophy in the Islamic world, Avicenna (he died in 1037). His impact was enormous and pervasive. So we find ‘theologians’ such as al-Ghazālī (died 1111) and Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī (died 1210) engaging in minute analysis of Avicenna’s arguments, accepting some aspects of the Avicennian system while finding fault with others. Al-Ghazālī is notorious for his critique of Avicenna’s metaphysics in TheIncoherence of the Philosophers, but he also heaped ridicule on anyone who denied the utility of the philosophers’ logic. As for al-Rāzī, his enormous theological compendia are comparable to those written by men such as Aquinas and Scotus in Latin Christendom, filled with scholastic argumentation and even structured in terms of philosophical elements like the Aristotelian categories. The myth that philosophy somehow died out in the Islamic world around the time of Averroes (died 1198) is in part the result of assuming that such texts fall outside the remit of the history of philosophy, despite being chock-full of intricate philosophical argumentation.

Read more

3 thoughts on “Did Rationalism Die In Islam With Averroes? Are Theologians Philosophers?

  1. Very interesting article.
    I need more time for in depth study.
    The following statement is from this article.
    ~~~~~~~
    Quote
    But my view is that philosophy is where you find it, and that it is narrow-minded to ignore philosophical argumentation put forward by thinkers simply because they have a religious agenda, whether that agenda grows out of Christianity (as with Aquinas), Judaism (as with Maimonides), Hinduism (as with Nyāya epistemology or Vedānta philosophy of mind), or Islam.
    Unquote
    ~~~~~~~
    The writer has equated:
    Christianity (as with Aquinas)
    Judaism (as with Maimonides)
    Hinduism (as with Nyāya epistemology or Vedānta philosophy of mind)
    Unfortunately the writer left Islam as is without any additinal info/name.
    Any additional info after “Islam” would have helped the reader to understand writer’s thought process.
    nSalik (Noor Salik)

    • The Author explains about Isalm in next paragraphs and includes in this category al-Ghazālī (died 1111) and Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī (died 1210)”
      Mirza Ashraf Sahib may be able to better comment on this article especially whether just reason and logic ( Socrates method) is enough to find philosophical truth ( Al-Ghazali, Aquinus) or in addition you also need demonstrative proof( Aristotelian-Aviceena, Averroes).
      Fayyaz

  2. In 1493, the Christians conquered Spain, ending eight centuries of Muslim rule. They massacred Muslims and Jews, and expelled many of them from Spain, but retained their philosophical and scientific works. In Baghdad, the crushing impact on the Muslim heartland by successive waves of invasions, led by the Turkic Seljuks, the Crusaders, the Ayyubid Kurds, the savage Mongols, and finally the Ottomans, gradually destroyed the centers of knowledge. Millions of books were thrown into the river by the Mongols and libraries were burned to ashes. Books and libraries are destroyed to create a vacuum of knowledge and cultural emptiness, so that the new rulers can build new societies. One of the most important reason for the loss of wealth of knowledge was that the Muslim rulers did not establish institutions like the House of Wisdom at Baghdad, in many other parts of their empire. They should have set up universities, colleges all over the world of Islam. Later caliphs, sultans, and monarchs who might have patronized and supported centers of learning focused instead on consolidating their positions and fighting battles.

    People in all walks of life looked for solace from the turmoil, massacre, and fierce foreign rule in religious thought and spirituality instead of philosophical argumentation. Muslim lands were now flooded with saints, and miracles became a part of everyday life. Thus, mysticism, known as Sufism, became an inclination and a sigh of relief for the Muslim masses. Sufism provided a new ideology to the caliphs and monarchs, particularly the newly-converted Mongol and Mughal rulers, who, instead of patronizing philosophical learning, began to patronize Sufi saints. Followers of Sufism would prove peace-loving and submissive subjects, who, instead of asking for their rights from their rulers, started seeking the blessings of saints who would pray for them. Belief in collective piety, hope, and confidence in God’s grace triumphed over the earlier concept of Classical Islam: “submission to God is submission to reason and reason could challenge the rulers.” Thus, a wave of individualistic quests for God engulfed the Muslims, seeking solace in prayers and in music as sama in the Sufic-inspired services.

    With the rise of Central Asian Turkic rulers, the Arabic language was replaced by Persian, and most philosophical works started appearing in the Persian language. Significant philosophical trends after ibn Sina were attempts to reconstruct holistic systems that refine rather than refute philosophical propositions and religious questions. A new trend in philosophy, the “Philosophy of Illumination” of Shihab al-Din Suhrawardy (1153-1191) appeared, second only to ibn Sina. This system defined a new method, the “Science of Lights,” which maintains that we obtain the principles of science immediately via “knowledge of presence.” Almost half a century after the execution of Suhrawardy, the philosophy of Illumination was viewed as a more complete system. Its aim was to expand the structure of Aristotelian philosophy to include carefully selected religious topics, defending the harmony between philosophy and religion. This gave rise to Mulla Sadra’s (1572-1641) theory of the unity or sameness of the knower and the known. Sadra’s view of theo-philosophy continues to influence philosophy even today.

    MIRZA ASHRAF

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.